Commentaries, Health February 6, 2017

Genetics Is Giving Way to a New Science of Life

by Jonathan Latham

by Jonathan Latham, PhD

Test your understanding of the living world with this simple question. What kind of large biomolecule is found in all living organisms? If your answer is “DNA”, you are incorrect. Some organisms contain no DNA at all.

The mistake is very forgivable though. A standard biology education casts DNA (DeoxyriboNucleic Acid) as the master molecule of life, coordinating and controlling most, if not all, living functions. This master molecule concept is popular. It is plausible. It is taught in every university and high school. But it is wrong. DNA is no master controller, nor is it even at the centre of biology. Instead, science overwhelmingly shows that life is self-organised. The science of biology is thus awaiting the paradigm shift to end all paradigm shifts.

The mythologising of DNA

Highly respected scientists make very strong claims for the powers of DNA. In his autobiography, Nobel Laureate Kary Mullis called it “The King of molecules” and “The big one”. Maybe he read DNA: The Secret of Life, a popular science book that calls DNA the molecule that “holds the key to the very nature of living things”. Its author should know. He is Nobel Laureate, James Watson, co-discoverer of the structure of DNA. Even institutions have strong opinions when it comes to DNA; the website of the US National Institutes of Health claims “Genes are at the center of everything that makes us human”.

My edition of The Secret of Life features on its back cover Eric Lander. Lander is the celebrated brains behind modern human genetics. He is also the head of the Broad Institute at MIT. In his blurb, Lander endorses “The secret of life” trope. Just below him on the jacket is Professor of genetics Mary-Claire King. She writes: “This is the story of DNA and therefore the story of life, history, sex, money, drugs, and still-to-be-revealed secrets.” According to Prof. King, DNA is life.

The Watsonian primacy of genetics dominates education too. The standard US high school biology textbook “Life“, of which we own the 1997 edition, frames the entirety of biology around DNA, thereby bestowing upon it the biochemical status of life’s centrepiece.

Phytoplankton
Phytoplankton (Image Credit: CodeCarvings)

Meanwhile, Francis Collins, longstanding head of the National Institutes of Health, has published bestselling books about DNA with titles like The Language of Life and the Language of God. It should be no surprise then that the idea of DNA as a master molecule is one of the dominant ideas of our age.

Some biologists will say that these views are extreme and unrepresentative. They are, and part of this article is to explain why extreme views about DNA dominate the upper echelons of science and public discourse. But its main purpose is to contrast the hyperbolic portrayal of DNA by virtually all biologists which is dissonant with the narrow scientific treatment they apply to other biological molecules. Our existence also depends on proteins, fats, carbohydrates and RNA (Ribonucleic Acid); but no one says “it’s in my protein”. But is it any less scientifically preposterous to say something “is in my DNA”?

To take a ruthless look at these questions is thus the purpose of this article. Does DNA have any claim to being in control? Or even just to be at the centre of biological organisation?

The answer is that DNA is none of the things Watson, Lander, and Collins claim above, even the standard, supposedly nuanced, biologist’s view of life is wrong. This is provable in many ways but mainly by a new science of life that is steadily emerging from almost complete obscurity. This new science explains the features of living beings in productive new ways that DNA-centric, genetic determinist, biology has not, and cannot. DNA, we will see, is not the language of God. It is not even the language of biology.

Organisms are systems

The evidence that DNA is not a biological controller begins with the observation that biological organisms are complex systems. Outside of biology, when we consider any complex system, such as the climate, or computers, or the economy, we would not normally ask whether one component has primacy over all the others. We consider it obvious that complex systems are composed of subsystems, each being necessary for the larger whole. Each subsystem has its specific niche but no one subsystem exerts a privileged level of causation.

Likewise, at the level of the physiology of an individual organism, we do not apply an exclusive or special causative role to any organ, neither the heart, nor the liver, or the skin, or the brain, because a body is a system. All parts are necessary.

So too at the smaller biological scales of organs, where distinct cell types maintain, operate, and repair themselves and each other. Similarly, at the cellular level, no one disagrees that organelles and other molecular structures are interacting but independent subparts of the whole.

At the level of macromolecules, however, a curious thing happens. Biologists abandon systems thinking entirely. Instead, we apply the famous central dogma of biology, which is that DNA makes RNA makes Protein (Crick, 1970). This formulation creates an origin story that begins with DNA.

The first mistake of the dogma, however, is to call it “central”. If an organism is a system, then there is no centre. The second error is that the pathway described is factually incorrect. The pathway should be a loop since the DNA does not come from nowhere: to make every DNA molecule requires proteins and RNA and DNA. More broadly, the synthesis of DNA cannot be done without a whole cell, just as the making of any RNA or any protein also takes a whole cell.

If we wanted to be more accurate still, we would say it takes a whole organism to make each of these components. Even this description would be incomplete, since, undeniably, it takes an ecosystem, including, in the case of humans, a gut microbiota and a food supply. The full formulation of the central dogma is therefore a loop embedded in a web. But the central dogma taught to millions of students every year takes an entirely different intellectual path. It arbitrarily confers on DNA a special place: firstly, by not closing the loop, and second, by placing DNA at its beginning. The central dogma is thus merely a representation formed from arbitrarily constructed boundaries. It is not biological reality.

Geneticists, and sometimes other biologists, make this linear interpretation seem plausible, not with experiments—since their results contradict it—but by using highly active verbs in their references to DNA. DNA, according to them, “controls”, “governs”, and “regulates” cellular processes, while nouns like “expression” are also commonly used to ascribe functions to DNA. Biologists thus confer activist and willful superpowers on DNA. Ultimately, this can create circular arguments. DNA controls embryonic development or organism health because genes express themselves. QED.

However, there is no specific science that demonstrates that DNA plays the dominant role these words imply. Quite the opposite. For example, a recent publication in Nature magazine posited “An emerging consensus that much of the protein constituent of the cell is buffered against transcriptional variation. ” i.e. is insulated from direct genetic quantitative influence (Chick et al., 2016). This buffering is nicely demonstrated by many experiments. One is the demonstration that the circadian rhythm of a bacterium can be reproduced, in the absence of any DNA, by just three proteins mixed together in a test tube. The rhythm was maintained for three days, even in the face of temperature changes (Nakajima et al., 2005).

Inevitably, any language used to describe DNA will necessarily be metaphorical and be of limited accuracy, but words like “govern” and “control” literally invent attributes for DNA (Noble, 2003). A much more precise metaphor for DNA would compare it to the library of Congress, since cells use DNA primarily as a storehouse of information. Consider that  biologists could apply more neutral verbs such as “use”, as in “cells use DNA to create proteins”. If so, they would have created a very different status for DNA. Only librarians would have T-shirts saying “its in my DNA”.

If we shed the wild metaphors and the central dogma, a more accurate way to think about biology emerges. If every molecule and every subsystem, regardless of scale, constrains and potentiates the other parts, then there is no need to infer a central controller. We can replace the DNA-centric model of biology with a relational model of complex interplay of feedback systems and emergent properties, of which the library of DNA is just one component. In this model, RNA is simply one of the inputs needed to make proteins and DNA is just one of the inputs needed to make RNA, and so on. Unlike the central dogma, such a proposition is consistent with the known facts of biology.

The formulation encapsulated by the central dogma and by biology textbooks is therefore an illusion. They are a classic case of what microbiologist Carl Woese has called the “reductionist fundamentalism”. Reductionist fundamentalism differs from simple reductionism in that whereas simple reductionism is a valid scientific method, the former is an ideological preference for a simplistic explanation when a more holistic one is better supported by the evidence. In this case, the assigning of superpowers to DNA to explain observed biological activities when a better explanation would accept that many biochemical events have multiple causes and contributors. Oxford physiologist Denis Noble describes this fallacy as conferring on DNA “a privileged level of causation”.

If not DNA, is there a “molecule of life”?

Many plant-infecting viruses lack DNA. They base their lifecycles on protein and they use RNA as their heritable material.

There are also plant pathogens, called viroids, that lack both DNA and protein. Viroids are thus composed solely of non-coding RNA. Lifeforms can therefore exist without either DNA or proteins—but there are none that that lack RNA.

Therefore, the answer to the opening question: “what kind of biomolecule is possessed by all living organisms?” is RNA. RNA stands for Ribonucleic Acid and for many reasons it is a better candidate for being a universal biomolecule than DNA.

RNA and DNA are chemically very similar. Even scientists confuse them, but their modest chemical distinctions confer very different properties. RNA is structurally very flexible (bendy), whereas DNA is highly inflexible; RNA is unstable and chemically reactive, whereas DNA is highly inert. A key difference is the number of chemical modifications that cells are able make to their four bases. In the case of DNA (whose bases are the nucleotides A,C,G and T), just two modifications are possible in most cells. These modifications are called methylation and acetylation. These two modifications alter the properties of DNA bases and they are the primary basis of the fashionable science of epigenetics.

RNA also has four bases (A, C, G, and U). But cells make more than one hundred comparable chemical modifications to them. The roles of these modifications are essentially a mystery, but presumably they help RNA perform its many cellular tasks.

RNA is also misunderstood. In a typical human cell, less than 1% of it makes proteins. The remaining 99% has a huge variety of structural, regulatory, and enzymatic functions. Most biologists though might as well be slaves to the central dogma in thinking that RNA is just the intermediate between DNA and protein. Only recently has RNA begun emerging from the shadow of DNA as a far more interesting molecule.

The deep explanation of these molecular differences is that RNA existed long before DNA. RNA probably predated even the invention of cells. It is enormously old. In consequence, it is so deeply and structurally embedded in living systems that it is very hard to study. Thus the paradoxical reason why we don’t know much about RNA is not because it is unimportant, but because, unlike DNA, RNA is too important to cell function to selectively remove at will.

Consequently, to conform with current evolutionary understanding, we should really invert standard teaching and insist that the proper way to think about DNA is that it is a specialised form of RNA. DNA evolved structural rigidity and chemical inertness to make itself a more staid librarian for the safe storing of heritable information.

So, over evolutionary time DNA was chosen as a better librarian (this library metaphor originates with Colin Tudge and his excellent book Why DNA isn’t selfish and people are nice); proteins turned out to be superior catalysts of chemical reactions; but RNA is more likely to have been the biomolecule around which life was really built. But RNA is no more a controller than is DNA.

Nor is DNA the centre of evolution

A common explanation for organising biology around DNA, and the one given by the authors of “Life“, the textbook, is DNA’s supposed role in the theory of evolution. For two reasons this explanation is highly questionable, however. Both reasons exemplify pervasive misunderstandings of the theory of evolution. One of these misunderstandings exaggerates the significance of Darwin’s theory and the second, once again, gives to DNA credit it doesn’t deserve.

The first misunderstanding is to assume that evolutionary theory is an explanation of life. Life, however, began long before Darwinian evolution and some of its fundamental patterns (cells, proteins, energy metabolism) emerged—so far as we can tell—long before DNA became the molecule of heredity (Carter, 2016). This distinction is important. In a textbook about “Life“, for example, it is important to separate the origin of life from its maintenance so as not to unhelpfully exaggerate (i.e. confuse) what Darwin’s theory explains; but in conflating the two, “Life” is only reflecting the misunderstanding of most biologists.

Second, the pre-Darwinian life of cells and metabolism arose thanks to the fact that complex systems have emergent and self-organising properties (e.g. Kauffman, 1993; Carter, 2016). The advent of DNA into these systems allowed Darwinian evolution to accelerate, but it did not eradicate emergent and self-organising properties. Rather, it colluded with them and helped create new ones. This means such properties are the likeliest explanation of large areas of biology. “Self-organization proposes what natural selection disposes” is how Batten and colleagues quaintly summarise alternatives to standard evolutionary theory which is pretty much rigidly genetic determinist (Batten et al., 2008).

A classic emergent property is the folding of proteins. DNA encodes the linear sequence of amino acids that constitute proteins, but every protein adopts one (or usually more) highly complex three dimensional shape (Munson et al., 1996). These shapes, along with charge and solubility, are largely responsible for a protein’s properties. It is habitually, but lazily, presumed that DNA specifies all the information necessary for the formation of a protein, but that is not true. All protein shapes depend also on the integration of multiple sources of information. These sources include temperature, other cellular molecules like water and mineral ions, pH, energy molecules like ATP, protein folding aids called chaperones, and so forth. Beyond this, many proteins have functions, such as to be molecular channels and pumps, that emerge only at higher levels of structure, such as in the presence of other proteins.

Thus DNA specifies proteins and their functions only up to a very limited point. It is possible to disregard all such non-genetic contributions and ascribe to DNA all the properties of a protein or a process (or a whole organism). Most scientists do, but doing so is an ultra-determinist position. It writes emergent properties, such as protein folding, entirely out of the functioning of life. It again confers onto DNA superpowers it does not have.

Emergent properties are only one example of why the relationship between DNA and evolution is much more tenuous than is normally portrayed. Patrick Bateson of Cambridge University, whose perspective is not emergent properties but animal behaviour, explained evolution much more accurately than most when he wrote: “Whole organisms survive and reproduce differentially and the winners drag their genotypes with them. This is the engine of Darwinian evolution“.

Thus we can explain why Charles Darwin invented his theory of evolution without knowing DNA even existed, because, even for evolution, DNA still is not “The big one”, but it is standard for biologists to teach that DNA is more important to evolution than any other component of living organisms.

Explaining genocentric biology

When Dorothy journeyed to the Emerald City she discovered that The Wizard of Oz was only “a common man”. He was devoid of magic powers and so could not help her friends. But there was at least something behind the facade. The same is true for DNA.

Most cellular molecules are highly reactive and transient chemical substances. That means they are difficult to extract, and hard to study. So it is with RNA and proteins.

DNA, however, is a much more practical point of intervention in biology. It is stable and robust and simple enough to be isolated on a reproducible basis and copied precisely. With an hour of training, high school students can do it. With a bit more training, DNA can be altered and, in some species, replaced. Hence the alarm over garage hacking of DNA.

This explains, in a nutshell, why our understanding of gene regulatory networks runs far ahead of our understanding of other disciplines of biology. It is because DNA is the low hanging fruit of biology.

Scientific dissent around DNA

“The human body completely changes the matter it is made of roughly every 8 weeks, through metabolism, replication and repair. Yet, you’re still you –with all your memories, your personality… If science insists on chasing particles, they will follow them right through an organism and miss the organism entirely.” mathematical biologist Robert Rosen is supposed to have said. And indeed, examine any multicellular organism and concealed under its relatively calm surface are circulatory systems, churning stomachs, lymphatic drainage systems, electrical impulses, biomolecular machines and so forth.

These systems cause every part of an organism to continuously move, contract, twist, vibrate, strain and grow. What defines living organisms, in the final analysis, is their dynamic and  animate nature. This is why, when we want to know if an organism has legally died we don’t examine its DNA, we measure its heartbeat or brain function. Animate properties require animate components, like RNA and proteins.

Yet by organizing our understanding of life largely around DNA (recall Mary-Claire King’s “DNA is life”), biologists have curiously chosen the cellular constituent that is probably the least representative of life’s dynamic nature.

For this reason there are dissenters in biology. Some are prominent. Some are not. They all have questioned whether biology is not much more complex and interesting than our present DNA-based framing can make room for (e.g. Kaufman, 1993; Strohman, 1997; Rose, 1999; Woese 2004; Annila and Baverstock 2014; Friston et al., 2015).

These dissenters like to note, for example, the general absence of medico-scientific breakthroughs following the sequencing of the human genome and the ever-more-detailed-analysis-of-tiny-scraps-of-human-DNA (Ioannidis, 2007; Dermitzakis and Clark, 2009; Manolio et al., 2009).

Some go much further in their critiques than others. Carl Woese, perhaps the best known bacteriologist since Pasteur, argued before his death that genetic determinism is a dead end, its vision of biology is “spent” (Woese, 2004).

There perhaps is no finer example of this than the field of tissue engineering. Tissue engineers claim to have made “incredible” progress making whole human organs in vitro for transplanting and other medical uses, yet these organs are all non-functional (Badylak, 2016). They don’t have blood vessels or immune systems or nerve networks, they are just human cells on an ear-shaped scaffold or a hand-shaped scaffold and so, among their many deficiencies, they are short-lived because they have no regenerative properties.

Many biologists suspect at least part of this paradigm problem, but they rarely act on it. The sole noticeable official response to the obvious fact that organisms are highly complex systems has been to shovel modest funding in the direction of ‘systems biology’.

One is bound to note that even this systems biology is rarely the study of systems. Instead, biologists have overwhelmingly used systems biology funds not to further the understanding of complex systems but to scale up and mechanise their reductionism.

Thus no scientific specialism or institution has articulated the profound inadequacy of viewing organisms as collections of gene regulatory networks or moved towards assembling an alternative paradigm (or paradigms) to replace it (Strohman, 1997).

This intellectual near-vacuum is nevertheless being steadily filled by individual scientists, mostly on the margins, with promising, even revolutionary, theoretical developments and experimental findings that explain biological phenomena in ways that transcend genetics.

A short guide to alternative paradigms of life

A Helmholtz machine is a sensory device that makes a prediction about reality and crosschecks it against that reality. It then estimates the difference between the two. Bayesian statistics is a mathematical method of doing the same: estimating differences between expectation and reality.

A new theory of neurobiology, called the Bayesian brain theory, proposes that the brain is the biological equivalent of these (reviewed in Clark, 2013). Brains make predictions, measure the mismatches with their expectations and pass those mismatches up to higher neural circuits. These higher circuits repeat the process and if mismatches persist then these are passed on to yet ‘higher’ mental levels.

The Bayesian brain hypothesis is quite new and predictive neurons might seem superficially improbable, yet the hypothesis appears to explain numerous aspects of brain structure and brain function; for example, how the brain can treat widely different stimuli (visual, sensual, oral, aural, etc.) essentially with the same neural mechanisms and structures. It also appears to show how the brain can integrate action and perception. The theory also provides a substantive explanation of learning: learning is the updating of the predictive model. The Bayesian brain hypothesis may even  explain how brains evolved higher levels of consciousness over evolutionary time periods: by adding new layers of prediction.

A particular strength of the Bayesian brain hypothesis is that it corresponds to the actual spatial organisation of neurons in the primate cortex in which ranks of “predictive” neurons and “sensory” neurons send signals in opposing directions which lets them cancel each other out (except for the mismatches).

The structure-based predictive learning system proposed by the Bayesian brain hypothesis is of interest here because it relegates detailed genetic explanations of many phenomena, including arguably all consciousness, to the margins (Friston, 2010). Genes and proteins may fill in the details but many of the key elements of brain function: learning, action, and perception, derive primarily from structure alone. I.e., like protein folding, they are emergent properties of organisation.

Emergent properties are equally important in other areas of biology. An example is the vascular system of plants. Trees can transport water from unsaturated sources hundreds of feet into the air. Transpiration, as it is called, requires no energy input. Rather, it takes advantage purely physical properties of hydrophilic xylem tissues (tubes) and the properties of water itself. Without transpiration, which already operates, but only very weakly, in soils, plants could not exceed a couple of inches in height, nor tolerate dry conditions (Wheeler and Stroock, 2008). Thus, the defining characteristic of plants (apart from photosynthesis) is their clever exploitation of a simple physical property of water.

A further example is the arches of the human foot. These are longitudinal and transverse diaphragms composed of bone and connective tissue whose emergent property is both to dissipate forces at impact and operate as springs to transfer energy from impact into forward motion. Arches reduce the energy needed to walk or run.

In the discipline of biochemistry, a recent development is the proposed existence of metabolons. Metabolons are three-dimensional spatial arrangements of enzymes. Metabolons explain how the product of an ostensibly minor metabolic pathway can nevertheless constitute 30% of the weight of a seedling and so drive away pests (Laursen et al., 2017).

A more conventional class of self-organising properties found in biology are homeostatic feedback loops. They too are phenomena largely independent of gene functions with key roles in explaining the activities and properties of living organisms. The three proteins noted earlier that can recreate a bacterial circadian rhythm are just one example (Nakajima et al., 2005).

At more elemental and universal levels of life are unifying theories of cells and metabolism, many of which relate life to the operation of fundamental physical forces. The father of all such theories was arguably Nicolas Rashevsky, who died in 1972. He is survived by his students Robert Rosen and AH Louie. Others include physicist Erwin Schrödinger, author of “What is life?“; Stuart Kauffman, author of “The Origins of Order” (1993); Steven Rose “Lifelines: Biology beyond determinism” (1997); Enrico Coen “The Art of Genes” (1999); Denis Noble, “The Music of Life” (2003) and Dance to the Tune of Life: Biological Relativity (2017); and Annila and Baverstock who argue life is the inevitable outcome of the second law of thermodynamics (Annila and Baverstock, 2014; see also Friston et al., 2015). These, and other omitted thinkers, have gone far in assembling the potential raw material for a scientific revolution. One that leaves the framework of gene regulatory networks far behind.

The closest that of any of these theories come to definitively falsifying genetic determinism as a life-concept, however, would be a theory of the origin of life itself that positions metabolism at the centre.

Readers may be familiar with the concept of the RNA world, which is theorised to have predated the supposed “modern DNA world”. But more convincing than an RNA world, for which there is little evidence, is a new theory, the peptide-RNA world.

The central piece of evidence of the peptide-RNA origin thesis (Carter, 2016) is that the enzyme (called aminoacyl-tRNA synthetase) that nowadays links RNA to proteins—and which therefore connects the RNA world to the protein world—comes in two basic forms (in all organisms). The evolutionary origin of these two forms (called Class I and Class II enzymes), however, is strangely irreconcilable. Class I and II molecules perform almost identical functions (though with different amino acids) yet have nothing structurally in common. Except for one thing. Their most conserved aminoacids, those at their active catalytic centre, can be derived from opposite strands of the same small RNA molecule (Carter 2016). In other words, the two proteins that let RNA make all modern proteins are derived from opposite strands of a single very primitive small RNA molecule that encoded them both.

The implication of this compelling observation is to intimately link metabolism and replication at a very early stage of life’s origins. RNA was the assembler of primitive proteins and the purpose of those proteins was catalysis, i.e. to guide and enhance metabolism. What the peptide-RNA origin thesis therefore does is to replaces the RNA world—which is a replication-first theory—with a metabolism-first theory in that RNA is enhancing a metabolism that already predated it.

DNA and politics

“Human biology is actually far more complicated than we imagine. Everybody talks about the genes that they received from their mother and father, for this trait or the other. But in reality, those genes have very little impact on life outcomes. Our biology is way too complicated for that and deals with hundreds of thousands of independent factors. Genes are absolutely not our fate. They can give us useful information about the increased risk of a disease, but in most cases they will not determine the actual cause of the disease, or the actual incidence of somebody getting it. Most biology will come from the complex interaction of all the proteins and cells working with environmental factors, not driven directly by the genetic code”. (Anand et al., 2008)

This quotation, spoken (but not written), by Craig Venter, the legendary genome sequencer, suggests that even many geneticists secretly appreciate a clear need for alternative paradigms.

At the same time the Venter quote prompts a deep question: How is it that, if organisms are the principal objects of biological study, and the standard explanation of their origin and operation is so scientifically weak that it has to award DNA imaginary superpowers of “expression” and “control” to paper over the cracks, have scientists nevertheless clung to it?

Why is it that, rather than celebrating and investing in Rashevsky, Kauffman, Noble, et al., as pioneers of necessary and potentially fruitful and unifying paradigms, have these researchers been ignored by mainstream biology?

What is the big attraction of genetic determinism?

A compelling and non-intuitive explanation for the monomania of biology does exist. It is set out in a second and forthcoming article: The Meaning of Life. It is an explanation that requires going behind the window dressing of science and examining its active and symbiotic relation to power in modern political systems.

References

Anand et al (2008) Cancer is a Preventable Disease that Requires Major Lifestyle Changes. Pharm Research 25: 2097–2116.
Annila, A and Baverstock K (2014) Genes without prominence: a reappraisal of the foundations of biology. DOI: 10.1098/rsif.2013.1017
Badylak, S (2016) Work with, not against, biology. Nature 540: S55 doi:10.1038/540S55a
Batten, D, S Salthe, F Boschetti (2008) Visions of evolution: self-organization proposes what natural selection disposes. Biological Theory 3: 17–29.
Carter, C (2016) An Alternative to the RNA World. Natural History Dec 2016/Jan 2017 28-33.
Chick JM, Munger SC, Simecek P, et al. (2016) Defining the consequences of genetic variation on a proteome-wide scale. Nature 534: 500-505.
Clark A, (2013) Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioural and Brain Sciences
Coen, E (1999) The Art of Genes. Oxford University Press.
Crick, F (1970) Central Dogma of Molecular Biology. Nature 227: 56–63.
Dermitzakis E.T. and Clark A.G. (2009) Life after GWA studies. Science 326: 239-240.
Friston K. (2010) The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11, 127-138 doi:10.1038/nrn2787
Friston K, M Levin, B Sengupta, G Pezzulo (2015) Knowing one’s place: a free-energy approach to pattern regulation.
Ioannidis J.P., Non-replication and inconsistency in the genome-wide association setting. Hum Hered, 2007. 64(4): p. 203-13.
Kaufman S (1993) The Origins of Order. Oxford University Press.
Laursen et al., (2017) Characterization of a dynamic metabolon producing the defense compound dhurrin in sorghum. Science 354: 890-895.
Manolio T. et al. (2009) Finding the missing heritability of complex diseases. Nature 461: 747-753.
Mullis K Dancing Naked in the Mind Field. 1998, Vintage Books.
M Munson, S Balasubramanian, KG Fleming et al. (1996) What makes a protein a protein? Hydrophobic core designs that specify stability and structural properties. Protein Science 5: 1584-1593.
Nakajima M. et al., (2005) Reconstitution of Circadian Oscillation of Cyanobacterial KaiC Phosphorylation in Vitro. Science 308: 414-15.
Noble D (2003) The music of life. Biology Beyond Genes. Oxford University Press.
Noble D (2017) Dance to the Tune of Life: Biological Relativity. Cambridge University Press.
Rose S (1997) Lifelines: Biology beyond Determinism. Oxford University Press.
Strohman RC (1997) The coming Kuhnian Revolution in biology. Nature Biotechnology 15: 194-200.
Tudge, Colin (2013) Why Genes are not Selfish and People are Nice. Floris books.
Watson JD (2003) DNA: The Secret of Life. Alfred A. Knopf.
Wheeler TD and A Stroock (2008) The transpiration of water at negative pressures in a synthetic tree. Nature 455, 208-212 doi:10.1038/nature07226
Woese CR (2004) A new biology for a new century. Microbiology and Molecular Biology Reviews, 68: 173-186.

If this article was useful to you please consider sharing it with your networks.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Comments 20
  • This is a very nice explanation of the (lacking) philosophy behind the field of systems biology.

    One area that you touch on but do have a chance to explore in detail is that alot of science is driven by what is possible rather than what is absolutely desirable. In terms of the DNA/RNA/protein/metabolite axis, it’s considerably easier to rapidly sequence whole genomes (all of the DNA in an organism) than it is to identify all of the proteins. One of the reasons for this – is of course the simplicity of “DNA” – a highly stable sequence of 4 different types of molecules. (Compare that to the 20 amino acids that make up our proteins – with their diverse chemical properties).

    This is also driven by industry and technology. Huge advances in the throughput of DNA sequencing “next-generation-sequencing”, often mean that scientific questions are framed around what can be done with the technology rather than attempting to answer the questions that are most relevant to the biology. As you point out, analysis of DNA is often the low hanging fruit in designing a biological experiment.

    Another driver in this area of biology is the co-occurrence or coincidence of different technological developments. In terms of the development of techniques for sequencing DNA at a massive scale, the development of computers and computational resources for processing, archiving and sharing that data have been absolutely critical. My point overall is that biological questions and the experiments that scientists design are strongly influenced by the available tools – and this is particularly evident in the current fields of large-scale and systems biology.

  • interesting as a new framing for everything – offers hope as a non predestined/Protestant understanding

  • Mindblowing!!! Thank you so much for this article. I learnt a whole lot of passionate things!
    A question emerged when reading your definition of life: then, are clouds, a star, a galaxy, a learning machine or the mantle of a planet forms of life? Because all of these present a “dynamic and animate structure”.
    Probably, such definitions of overused terms like “life” are not very relevant, and much less appreciable than learning biological processes and theories, even the more so when one embraces a holistic approaches. But it still intrigues me how we can properly define “life” (maybe from one of its necessary element, like cells or RNA — but that’s again reductionist), and if makes sense to find a definition in the sole aim to fit our previous conceptions (namely, life is all that is falls in a biological kingdom).

  • Actually, a librarian’s shirt would probably say “It’s in my DNA” (not “Its in my DNA”).

  • I detect an agenda here. I am not a scientist and at 66 I was around when Watson et al unraveled the DNA model and learned something about it as I went along.

    None of this is in any way controversial to me. I have never been taught that DNA is in “control”, only that it encodes the instructions for a living organism to replicate and repair its own structures and from which its processes derive. The classic example is the genetically identical twins who have different finger prints because the DNA only tells the already-living organism HOW to build itself and is not a blueprint to which it MUST adhere.

    The discovery of the iterative process for skin colour and its dependence both on the point in gestation at which the iterations start and the size of the animal concerned also makes clear both that it is not a blueprint, it is not in control and allows for errors in the process that produce unexpected differences.

    I was also taught, from the beginning, that RNA preceded DNA, this is not news even to a non-scientist. Hence my interest in what your actual point is.

    As for the DNA focus on proteins, I agree, it appears to be silly, given that, apart from protein synthesis there is a lot of so-called “junk” material that almost certainly would have some role to play in development but is still opaque to science.

  • Thanks for an excellent, learned, comprehensive, and thought-provoking review.

    One reason (of many) for the persistence of current, possibly-mistaken, paradigms in biology is indeed politics. The bankers and the Deep State who are our real rulers wish to control every facet of our lives. They have deliberately taken over the media, book publishing, medicine, the three branches of the American government. They are likewise in the process of taking over and corrupting food production. And they have taken over, by now, the entire scholarly enterprise, at least in the West. They chose and promoted, behind the scenes, the biological worldview that rules biology today, and they will see to it that it remains in place. See for instance: http://drnissani.net/mnissani/pagepub/HISTORY.HTM

  • “For example, a recent publication in Nature magazine posited “An emerging consensus that much of the protein constituent of the cell is buffered against transcriptional variation. ” i.e. is insulated from direct genetic quantitative influence (Chick et al., 2016).”
    As co-first author on this study, I would like to correct the record on your takeaway from our paper. While it does appear that many proteins are buffered against variation in their own transcript, we showed that the abundance of these proteins is often tied to the transcript and protein abundance of a second, physically interacting protein – importantly, we find DNA variants that likely underlie these transcriptional differences. So while the “buffered” protein may be insulated from its own transcriptional variation, it is still under the direct genetic quantitative influence of another protein. And while I appreciate your reference to our article, let me unequivocally state that our study found no evidence that the protein and transcript expression differences observed in our diverse genetic population stemmed from any other causal difference than DNA variants. In fact, we were able to identify causal mediator proteins in our analysis only because we could use the DNA in our QTL analyses as the causal anchor for our mediation analysis. Of course you’re welcome to your own conclusion on the significance of DNA to life, but please don’t cite our paper as evidence for that view. It is anything but.

    • Hi Steven, I did realise that your paper was pointing in a different direction to the general point I was trying to make. I wanted the readers to know, however, that there was a consensus (as referred to in your Chick et al. introduction) but also some dispute about that consensus. I appreciate it is not a standard referencing style and I hope you are not too offended by the imputation that you or your paper supports the consensus when you think it does not. I could have been clearer about that in the text and your response suggests I should have been. However, on a bigger point, your statements actually speak to the whole issue rather well. The big question is, does your discovery of DNA variants that underlie these transcriptional differences show a special role for DNA and prove after all that transcripts are under genetic control? I don’t think so, 1) because DNA variants you identified, to which you attribute causality, are ones whose actions are mediated by proteins, which you acknowledge. 2) the DNA variants behind those proteins are themselves mediated by protein action. I would argue therefore, far from generating evidence of genetic causation, your research showed that the chain of causation stretches back through many causes and makes the general point of the article quite well. This is not to dispute any statements you make, however. The influence on the transcripts you study is mediated, depending on how you decide to frame it, by DNA variants. But the key thing is that, to come to that conclusion depends on framing, and not strictly on science. So your paper is a classic case of deciding you have an answer when the trail of causation goes back to DNA and stopping there.

      • Hi Jonathan, the reason that the trail of causation stops at the DNA in our study is because we can show that the cause of the observed variance in protein abundance is a DNA variant that is located close to a gene and acts in cis to affect its expression. Of course there are proteins that bind that DNA to drive expression of that gene, but those proteins act on both alleles, while it is the cis DNA variation that causes the differential expression observed in our population. I haven’t read all of your articles, so I can’t speak to your ideas more broadly, but in this specific study we found no evidence for any mechanism other than genetic causation. If changes in the DNA did not explain the observed variance in transcript and protein abundance, I would not have stopped looking for another viable cause. -Steve

        • Hi Steve, there is no reason not to take the explanation back further though. Maybe those changes in DNA were enabled by the evolution of transcription factors able to recognise one allele and not others. Or maybe you wouldn’t get the same results under other conditions. I am not trying to be funny with you, just trying to show that your definition of the words “cause” is arbitrary. There is a continuous loop of genetic/protein/genetic/protein/genetic/etc. explanations depending on how far one chooses to go back and that stopping with genes is arbitrary and unwarranted. Thanks for your attention. PS I recommend for you todays article: https://www.independentsciencenews.org/health/the-meaning-of-life-part-i/

          • Forgive me in advance for questioning your motives here, but I’ve honestly never met someone who adheres to this particular view. Do you really believe this? If yes, is there a specific reason why you favor it? It seems to me from a short scan of some of your articles that you truly do believe it, and are not just in it to sell books. But to this outsider who has never been exposed to this side of the science internet before, I’m surprised by how deep you’ve dug this rabbit hole and the level of conspiratorial thinking (e.g. Rockefeller Nucleic Acid) you’re willing to entertain to push this theory. I’m genuinely impressed by the effort if not the misinformation, and I promise I’m not trolling.

          • Well, the reader can decide if genetic determinism is more or less of a rabbit hole than a holistic view of life. When I was in academia I subscribed to roughly your view but I steadily came to see it was troublingly full of holes and the harder I looked the bigger those holes came to seem. Gradually I became a critic of GWA studies (and twin studies). Less a year ago I came to write this article (which has now mushroomed into three articles!) and in the process came to see that the whole of biology was falsely framed around DNA and genetics. I have two suggestions for you to read:
            The Strohman article http://harveybialy.org/files/kuhn.pdf
            and
            Charney E, and English W (2012) Candidate Genes and Political Behavior. American Political Science Review 106: 1-34. (https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055411000554)
            Its not a rabbit hole and these are absolutely compelling critiques.
            As to motivation, genetic determinism is a denial of human and natural possibilities. It is killing us. Take a look at what happens to research programmes when they step outside the genetic paradigm and tell me this is not impressive or necessary:
            How Millions of Farmers are Advancing Agriculture For Themselves (https://www.independentsciencenews.org/un-sustainable-farming/how-millions-of-farmers-are-advancing-agriculture-for-themselves/)
            yours sincerely, Jonathan

  • Jonathan, don’t mistake my critiques here as an endorsement of genetic determinism. That’s a huge leap from acknowledging the fact of *genetic predisposition*. The last time I checked, you don’t have to deny the importance of DNA as the molecule of heredity to advocate against genetic determinism. For even the most heritable phenotypes, environment plays a huge role. I share your concern when I hear people overstate the importance of genetics in defining any physiological or behavioral phenotype, but the flip side of that coin – to deny that DNA is the genetic molecule of heredity – seems equally ill-informed and troubling. BTW, I was also a critic of GWA studies early on, but realized most of my issues were directed at the tone of the press releases about these studies. They made it seem that these common variants were controlling much of the phenotypic diversity, but any individual common variant (aside from Apoe4) underlies very little of the observed variation in the measured phenotype across the population. That doesn’t mean those studies weren’t useful, as they identified genes that likely have roles in disease onset or progression and therefore may be good targets for therapeutic intervention. Do you believe that acknowledging a genetic predisposition for certain phenotypes is a tacit or explicit endorsement of genetic determinism? -Steve

    • Hi Steven. Did you read the articles? I define genetic determinism as the assertion of genetic causes when there is no evidence one way or the other. The causes in your paper are multifactorial but your paper asserted exclusively genetic causes, as did your comments here. So I don’t have any trouble saying your position is one of genetic determinism. This is not to single your views out. Our whole society is genetic determinist, and that is my point. We don’t have to be, and its dangerous. I would appreciate hearing your definition. Maybe it is different and would explain a lot. Thank you for sharing your views.

  • Excellent article, Jonathan! Good claims to challenging DNA’s role as the master molecule. However, your article seems to be based on a belief in the theory of evolution, which is another theory which needs to be called into question. So many people think it began with Darwin but it did not. Ancient cultures also believed in a similar origin to life emerging from “water” or primordial “soup.” What I find disturbing with evolutionary science is all the funding put into its theories trying to figure out what evolved into what and how the order of molecular evolution might affect us today. Like, how relevant is such speculation? So what if RNA came before DNA? So much easier to believe that an amazing Intelligent Being (God) created ex nihilo this awesome world and our job as scientists is to explore His creation and produce technologies and healing to bless mankind. I maintain a scientist does not need evolutionary explanations/theories to be a topnotch scientist. But that’s my belief, and we all choose to believe what we want to believe.

  • A very perceptive and convincing article. I read, years ago, a book called “the web of life” by Fritjof Capra which I found fascinating. In fact, together with Platos “Phaedo” and “Republic”, these three works made me study philosophy.

    He points towards Ilya Prigogine, Franceco Varela and Humberto Maturana, theoricians of cybernetics. They invented the concept of “autopoiesis” litteraly “self-creation” and the concept of “dissipative structures”. It seems to me what you say about RNA fits these conceptions quite nicely.
    These concepts are exceedingly powerful, yet have not seeped into the realm of political thought yet (!).
    To use Prigogines terminology, an autopoietic system (DNA-RNA) is being described as an allopoietic system (a factory is such a system: raw materials/components come in, a assembled fully functional product comes out).

Leave a comment

*

*